Chapter I The causes of war: First, defence of self and property
169-185
I. What causes of war may be called justifiable
169-171
II. Justifiable causes include defence, the obtaining of that which belongs to us or is our due, and the inflicting of punishment
171-172
III. War for the defence of life is permissible
172-173
IV. War in defence of life is permissible only against an actual assailant
173
V. War in defence of life is permissible only when the danger is immediate and certain, not when it is merely assumed
173-175
VI. Defence of limb against injury is also justifiable
175
VII. The defence of chastity is in the highest degree justifiable
175
VIII. Not to take advantage of the right of defence is permissible
176
IX. Defence is sometimes not permissible against a person useful to the state because at variance with the law of love
176-177
[105] X. It is not permissible for Christians to kill in order to ward off a blow, or to avoid any indignity of like sort, or to prevent any escape
178-179
XI. By the law of nature it is permissible to kill in defetice of property
179
XII. How far defence of property is permitted by the law of Moses
180-182
XIII. Whether, and under what limitations, it is permissible, according to the law of the Gospel, to kill in defence of property
182
XIV. Whether the civil law, in permitting that life be taken in self-defence, confers a right, or merely freedom from punishment, is discussed, with a noting of distinctions
183
XV. When a single combat may be permissible
183
XVI. Concerning defence in public war
184
XVII. A public war is not admitted to be defensive which has as its only purpose to weaken the power of a neighbour
184
XVIII. A public war is not admitted to be defensive on the part of him who has himself given just cause for war
185
Chapter II Of things which belong to men in common
186-205
I. The division of that which is our own
186
II. The origin and development of the right of private ownership
186-190
III. That certain things, such as the sea both as a whole and in its principal divisions, cannot become subject to private ownership, and why
190-191
IV. That unoccupied lands become the property of the individuals who become occupants of them, unless they have been taken over as a whole by a people
191-192
V. That wild animals, fish, and birds belong to the man who has caught them, unless a law forbids
192
VI. That in case of necessity men have the right to use things which have become the property of another, and whence this right comes
193-194
VII. That the right, in case of necessity, to use things belonging to others, holds when the necessity is in no way avoidable
194
VIII. That the right, in case of necessity, to use things belonging to another, holds except when the possessor has equal need
194-195
IX. That there is, further, an obligation to restore the things of another used in case of necessity, whenever restoration shall be possible
195
X. Application of this right in the case of wars
195
XI. That men possess the right to use things which have become the property of another, for a purpose which involves no detriment to the owner
196
XII. Hence the right to the use of running water
196
XIII. Hence, also, the right of passage over land and rivers, with explanation
196-200
XIV. Whether a tax may be imposed upon merchandise passing through a country
200-201
[120] XV. The right of temporary sojourn
201
XVI. Those who have been driven from their homes have the right to acquire a permanent residence in another country, in submission to the government there in authority
201-202
XVII. The right of possession over desert places in respect to foreigners, and how this must be understood
202-203
XVIII. The right to such acts as human life requires
203
XIX. The right to such acts as human life requires includes the right to buy the things that are necessary
203-204
XX. The right to such acts as human life requires does not oblige a man to sell what belongs to him
204
XXI. The right to such acts as human life requires includes the right to seek marriages in foreign countries ; explanation
204
XXII. The right to do those things which are permitted without distinction to foreigners
204-205
XXIII. Such a right must be understood as applying only to things permitted as it were by the law of nature, not granted as a favour
205
XXIV. Whether a contract is permissible with a people that it should sell its crops to those with whom it has made the contract, and not to others
205-
Chapter III Of original acquisition of things, with special reference to the sea and rivers
206-219
I. That original acquisition is accomplished through division or through occupation
206
II. In this connexion other modes of acquisition, as the granting of an incorporeal right, are excluded from consideration
206
III. The forming of a new property from existing materials is also excluded from consideration
206
IV. Occupation is twofold, having relation to sovereignty and to ownership ; this distinction is explained
206-207
V. That the taking possession of movable things can be prevented by law
207-208
VI. On what right the ownership of property by infants and by insane persons rests
208
VII. That rivers can be acquired by occupation
208-209
VIII. That a part of the sea can likewise be acquired
209
IX. That formerly in the countries constituting the Roman Empire such ownership of a part of the sea was not conceded
209-210
X. That nevertheless the law of nature does not present any obstacle to such acquisition in respect to a part of the sea which is, as it were, shut in by lands
210-211
XI. In what way such possession may be taken, and, how long it will last
212
XII. That such possession does not give the right to impede innocent passage
212
XIII. That sovereignty can be acquired over a part of the sea, and in what way
212-214
XIV. That for certain reasons a tax can be laid upon those who sail upon the sea
214-215
XV. Of the agreements which forbid a people to sail beyond certain bounds
215-216
XVI. Whether or not a change in the course of a river involves a change of territory is set forth, with a distinction
216-217
XVII. What conclusion is to be reached if the bed of a river has been completely changed
217-218
XVIII. That sometimes an entire river belongs to a territory
218
XIX. That things which have been abandoned become the property of him who takes possession of them, unless a state has acquired a general right of ownership over them
218-219
Chapter IV On assumed abandonment of ownership and occupation consequent thereon ; and wherein this differs from ownership by usucaption and by prescription
220-230
[138] I. Why ownership by usucaption or by prescription properly so called does not occur between states or their rulers
220
II. That nevertheless possession of long standing is wont to be urged as a right even between states or rulers
220-221
III. The question is decided according to presumptions of human intent ; and these presumptions are not based on words alone
221
IV. But such presumptions are based also on acts
221-222
V. Such presumptions are based also on things not done
222-223
VI. How length of time together with non-possession and silence amounts to an abandonment of right
223
VII. Time exceeding the memory of man ordinarily suffices for such a presumption ; of what sort such time is
224
VIII. Answer to the objection, that no one ought to be assumed to abandon his right
224-225
IX. Without such presumption it seems that by universal customary law ownership is transferred by possession exceeding the memory of man
226
X. Whether unborn children can in like manner be deprived of a right
226-227
XI. Even the right of sovereignty is gained by a people or king by long-standing possession
227-228
XII. Whether the civil statutes concerning ownership by usucaption and by prescription bind the one who holds sovereign power ; explanation, with distinctions
228-229
XIII. Those rights of sovereignty which can be separated from it, or shared with others, are gained and lost by right of ownership based on usucaption or on prescription
229
XIV. Refutation of the opinion alleging that subjects are always allowed to assert their liberty
229-230
XV. Whatever belongs to faculty pure and simple is not lost by lapse of time ; explanation
230
Chapter V On the original acquisition of rights over persons. Herein are treated the rights of parents, marriage, associations, and the rights over subjects and slaves
231-259
I. Concerning the rights of parents over children
231
II. Distinction in respect to the period of infancy, and concerning the ownership of property by infants
231-232
III. Of the period of life in the family beyond infancy
232
IV. Concerning the right of restraining children
232
V. Concerning the right of selling children
232-233
VI. Of the period of life beyond infancy and outside of the family
233
VII. Distinction between the power of parents by the law of nature and that by the municipal law
233-234
VIII. Concerning the right of the husband over the wife
234
IX. Whether denial of divorce and restriction to one woman are necessary to marriage according to the law of nature or only according to the law of the Gospel
234-237
X. That according to the law of nature alone marriages are not void by reason of lack of consent of the parents
237-239
XI. That according to the law of the Gospel marriages with the husband or wife of another are void
239
XII. That according to the law of nature marriages of parents with children are unlawful and void
239-241
XIII. That marriages of brothers with sisters, mothers-in-law with sons-in-law, fathers-in-law with daughters-in-law, and other similar marriages are unlawful and void by volitional divine law
242-245
XIV. That the same objection does not seem to hold in case of marriages with relatives of a degree farther removed
245-247
XV. That certain marriages, which are classed by the laws as concubinage, can take place and are lawful
247-248
XVI. That certain marriages can be unlawfully contracted and nevertheless be valid
248-249
XVII. The right of the majority in associations of any kind
249-250
XVIII. Which opinion should prevail in case of a tie vote
250
XIX. What opinions should be divided and what joined
250-251
XX. That the right of those who are absent accrues to those present
252
XXI. What rank is to be observed among equals, even kings
252
XXII. In associations which are based upon property, the votes must be counted according to the shares which each has in the property
252-253
XXIII. The right of a state over its subjects
253
XXIV. Whether it is permissible for nationals to withdraw from a state ; explanation, with a distinction
253-254
XXV. The state has no legal claim against exiles
254
XXVI. The right, arising from consent, over an adopted child
255
XXVII. The right over slaves
255-256
XXVIII. To what extent the right of life and death may be said to exist in the right over slaves
256
XXIX. What according to the law of nature should be decided concerning those who are born of slaves?
256-258
XXX. Different kinds of slavery
258
XXXI. The right gained by consent over a people which submits
258
XXXII. The right over a person resulting from a crime
259
Chapter VI On secondary acquisition of property by the act of man ; also, alienation of sovereignty and of the attributes of sovereignty
260-266
I. What is necessary, on the part of the giver, that the alienation of a right should be valid
260
II. What is necessary on the part of the receiver
260-261
III. That sovereignty can be alienated, sometimes by the king, sometimes by the people
261
IV. That sovereignty over a part of a people cannot be alienated by the people against the will of the part
261
V. That a part cannot alienate the sovereignty over itself except in case of extreme necessity
261-262
VI. The reason for the difference indicated
262
VII. That sovereignty over a place can be alienated
262-
VIII. Refutation of the opinion that a king can lawfully alienate portions of his dominion for reasons of advantage or necessity
263
IX. That infeudation and pledging are contained in alienation
263
X. That for alienating inferior powers also the consent of the people is required, either express or inferred from custom
263-264
XI. That the public domain cannot be alienated by kings
264
XII. That it is necessary to distinguish the income arising out of public domains from the domains themselves
264
XIII. To what extent parts of the public domain can be pledged by kings, and why
265
XIV. That a will is a form of alienation and formed upon the law of nature
265-266
Chapter VII On derivative acquisition of property which takes place in accordance with law; and herein, intestate succession
267-294
I. That certain laws of states are unjust and. therefore do not transfer ownership ; such as those which confiscate the goods of shipwrecked persons in favour of the state treasury
267
II. That according to the law of nature property is justly acquired by a man who has received another's property to satisfy a debt ; when this may take place
267-268
III. How intestate succession has its origin in nature
269
IV. Whether any of the property of parents is due to children according to the law of nature ; explanation, with a distinction
269-271
V. That in a succession children are preferred to the father and mother of the deceased, and why
271-272
VI. The origin of vicarious succession, which is called representation, or succession in the place of and with the rights of another
272-273
VII. On abdication and disinheritance
273
VIII. Concerning the rights of illegitimate children
273-274
IX. When there is neither a will nor a precise law covering the matter, if there are no children the ancestral property should be returned to those from whom it came, or to their children
275-276
X. Possessions recently acquired go to the nearest relatives
277-278
XI. Diversity of laws about succession
278-279
XII. What is the manner of succession in hereditary kingdoms
279-
XIII. That if hereditary kingdoms are indivisible the eldest child is given preference
280
XIV. That in case of doubt a kingdom which is hereditary only with the consent of the people is indivisible
281
XV. That the right to such kingdoms does not continue beyond the last descendants of the first king
281-282
XVI. That in such kingdoms illegitimate children have no right of succession
282
XVII. That in such a kingdom male descendants are preferred to female descendants of the same degree of relationship
282
XVIII. That among the male descendants the eldest is given preference
282-283
XIX. Whether such a kingdom is a part of an inheritance
284
XX. That the presumption is that such a form of succession was established in the kingship as was customary in other things at the time of the founding of the kingdom. First, if the royal power is free from rights of tenure
284
XXI. Secondly, if the royal power is held as a fief
284-285
XXII. What cognate lineal succession is; and of what character the transmission of right in it is
285-286
XXIII. What agnate lineal succession is
286
XXIV. The succession in which nearness of relationship to the first king is always considered
286-287
XXV. Whether a son can he disinherited in respect to succession to the throne
288
XXVI. Whether any one can abdicate the throne for himself and his children
288-289
XXVII. Absolute decision regarding the succession belongs neither to the king nor the people
289-290
XXVIII. That a son born before the father came to the throne should have preference over one born afterward
290
XXIX. The rule stated holds unless it appears that the kingship was conferred under a different condition
290-291
XXX. The question whether the son of an older son is to be given preference to a younger son ; explanation, with a distinction
291-293
XXXI. Likewise, whether a surviving younger brother of the king ought to be given preference over the son of an older brother
293
XXXII. Whether the son of a brother should be preferred to an uncle of the king
293
XXXIII. Whether the son of a son should have preference over the daughter of a king
293
XXXIV. Whether a younger grandson, born of a son, has preference over an older grandson, born of a daughter
293-294
XXXV. Whether a granddaughter born of an older son should be preferred to a younger son
294
XXXVI. Whether the son of a sister ought to be preferred to the daughter of a brother
294
XXXVII. Whether the daughter of an older brother takes precedence over a younger brother
294
Chapter VIII On acquisitions commonly said to be by the law of nations
295-309
I. That many rights are said to have their origin in the law of nations, of which, if we speak accurately, this is not true
295-296
II. That fish in ponds and wild animals confined in parks are private property according to the law of nature, contrary to the ruling of the Roman law
296
III. That wild beasts, even if they have escaped, are none the less the property of those who captured them, if they can be properly identified
296-297
IV. Whether possession may be acquired with the help of appliances, and how?
297
V. That it is not contrary to the law of nations that wild creatures should be the property of kings
297-298
VI. How the possession of other things lacking an owner may be acquired
298
VII. Tο whom a treasure-trove naturally falls ; the diversity of the laws on this subject
298-299
VIII. That the regulations of the Roman law regarding islands and alluvial deposits belong neither to the law of nature nor to the law of nations
299-300
IX. That by the law of nature an island in a river and a dried out bed belong to the one who owned the river or the part of the river, that is, to the people
300-301
X. That by the law of nature in an inundation the ownership of the land is not lost
301-302
[200] XI. That in cases of doubt alluvial deposits also belong to the people
302-303
XII. But that such alluvial deposits seem to be conceded to those whose lands have no other boundary than the river
303
XIII. That the same opinion is to be held in regard to a bank abandoned by a river, and a part of the bed that has dried out
303-304
XIV. What is to be considered alluvial deposit and what an island
304
XV. When alluvial deposits belong to vassals
304-305
XVI. Answer to the arguments by which the Roman jurists defend their law as the law of nature
305
XVII. Naturally a road prevents gain by alluvial addition
305-306
XVIII. That it is not according to nature that the ownership of the offspring should be determined from the mother alone
306
XIX. That according to nature a thing fashioned out of another's material becomes common property in the same manner as in the intermingling of properties
306-307
XX. The principle stated holds true even if the material has been intentionally injured
307
XXI. That it is not natural that a thing of less value should be absorbed by one of greater worth on account of superiority in value. Here also errors of the Roman jurists are noted
307
XXII. That by planting, sowing, or building on another’s ground a community of ownership naturally is produced
308
XXIII. That in community of ownership a person who merely has possession of a thing is not entitled to the income of it, but can charge for expenses incurred
308
XXIV. The same right holds even if possession has been obtained fraudulently
308
XXV. That actual delivery is not required naturally in order to establish transfer of ownership
308-309
XXVI. The application of what has thus far been said
309
Chapter IX When sovereignty or ownership ceases
310-319
I. Ownership and sovereignty cease when he who possessed the right is taken away and leaves no successor
310
II. Similarly the rights of a family are extinguished when the family dies out
310
III. So also the rights of a people are extinguished if the people ceases to exist
310-312
IV. Such extinction takes place if the essential parts have been destroyed
312-313
V. The rights of a people are extinguished when the body of the people as a whole is broken up
313
VI. The rights of a people are extinguished when the form of organization, under which the people exists, is destroyed
313-314
VII. The rights of a people are not extinguished by reason of migration
314
VIII. Such rights are not extinguished by a change of government; and herein also the question of what is due to a new king or to a liberated people is treated
314-315
IX. What becomes of such rights if peoples are joined together ?
315
X. What becomes of such rights if a people is divided ?
315-316
XI. Who is now possessor of the rights which once belonged to the Roman Empire, in so far as they do not appear to have been alienated ?
316-319
XII. Concerning the rights of heirs
319
XIII. Concerning the rights of the conqueror
319
[214] Chapter X On the obligation which arises from ownership
320-327
I. The origin and nature of the obligation to restore the property of another to its owner
320-322
II. The obligation to restore any gain that a person has made from another’s property ; this is illustrated by many examples
322-324
III. That a person who has honestly come into possession of another's property is not bound to make restitution, if the property has perished
324
IV. That such a possessor of another's property is bound to restore the income that still remains
324
V. That such a possessor is likewise bound to make good the income which has been used up, if under other circumstances he would have used an equivalent
324
VI. That such a possessor is not bound to restore income which he neglected to collect
324
VII. That such a possessor is not bound to make restitution of the property which he has given to another ; herewith a distinction
325
VIII. That such a possessor, again, is not under obligation if he has sold a thing which he has bought ; likewise herewith a distinction
325
IX. When a person, who in good faith has bought property of another, can reserve the cost, or a part thereof
325-326
X. That purchased goods, if they belong to another, cannot rightfully be returned to the seller
326
XI. That a person who has in his possession property of which the owner is unknown is not bound to turn it over to any one
326
XII. That according to the law of nature money received for a shameful cause, or under other circumstances for an act which one is under obligation to perform, does not have to be restored
327
XIII. Refutation of the opinion that ownership of goods which are weighed, counted, or measured, changes without the consent of the owner
327
Chapter XI On promises
328-342
I. Refutation of the opinion that by the law of nature a right does not arise from promises
328-330
II. That bare assertion does not create a binding obligation
330
III. That by the law of nature a promise is binding, but that no legal right is thereby gained by another
330
IV. What the kind of promise is by which a second party acquires a legal right
330-332
V. That for a perfect promise the possession of reason on the part of the promisor is requisite ; herein the law of nature is distinguished from the civil statutes in regard to minors
332-333
VI. Whether a promise given under a misapprehension is by the law of nature binding, and to what extent
333-334
[223] VII. That a promise made under the influence of fear is binding, but that the person who caused the fear is under obligation to secure the release of the promisor
334-335
VIII. That, in order that a promise may be valid, that which is promised ought to be within the power of the promisor
335
IX. Whether by the law of nature a promise to do an illegal act is binding ; explanation, with a distinction
335-336
X. What should be thought of a promise made to obtain a thing which was already due before the promise
336
XI. The method of making a firm and binding promise in person
336-337
XII. The method of making a binding promise through the agency of others ; also concerning ambassadors who exceed their powers
337
XIII. To what extent obligations incurred through the agency of ship-captains and through business agents arise from the law of nature ; wherein also an error of the Roman law is pointed out
337-338
XIV. That the acceptance of a promise is necessary to make it binding
338
XV. Whether an acceptance ought to be made known to the promisor ; explanation, with a distinction
338
XVI. That a promise can be revoked if the one to whom it was made died before accepting it
338-339
XVII. Whether a promise is revoked on the death of an intermediary ; explanation, with distinctions
339-340
XVIII. Whether a promise is revocable after acceptance by a proxy ; explanation, with distinctions
340-341
XIX. At what time a burdensome condition can be added to a promise
341
XX. How an invalid promise can be made binding
341
XXI. That promises without cause are not void by the law of nature
341
XXII. To what degree a person who has promised an act of another is bound by the law of nature
342
Chapter XII On contracts
343-361
I. The division of men’s acts which are advantageous to other men; first, into simple acts and acts of a mixed character
343
II. The division of simple acts into those that are merely acts of kindness and those that involve a mutual obligation—
343
III. Also into reciprocal acts, which sometimes separate the parties
343-345
IV. Reciprocal acts that sometimes contribute to a community of interests
345-346
V. That acts of mixed character may be mixed in respect to their main elements
346
VI. Or such acts may be of mixed character only by reason of an additional act
346
VII. What acts are called contracts
346
VIII. That equality is required in contracts ; and first, equality as regards preceding acts
346-347
IX. That equality is required, in contracts as regards knowledge of the facts
347-348
X. That equality is required in contracts as regards freedom of choice
348
XI. Secondly, that equality is required in the act oj making a contract, if it be a contract requiring an exchange
349
XII. Thirdly, there should be equality in the subject of the contract ; explanation thereof
349-350
XIII. What equality ought to obtain in acts that are wholly acts of kindness, or partly acts of kindness
350-351
XIV. In what way the price of an object ought to be estimated in a sale, and for what reasons it may justly increase or decrease
351-352
XV. When according to the law of nature a sale is completed, and when ownership is transferred
352-353
XVI. What monopolies are contrary to the law of nature or the law of love
353
XVII. How money serves as the medium of exchange
354
XVIII. By the law of nature nothing should be deducted from the price of rent on account of unfruitfulness or similar misfortunes ; also what rule holds if the first renter is hindered from using a thing and it has been rented by another
354-355
XIX. How a just payment for services may be increased or diminished
355
XX. By what right interest is forbidden
355-357
XXI. What advantages do not come under the head of interest
357
XXII. What the force of the civil laws is in this matter
358
XXIII. What valuation ought to be put on a contract for securing against loss or insuring
358
XXIV. What rule applies in the case of a partnership ; wherein many kinds of partnerships are explained
358-359
XXV. Concerning joint undertakings for maritime operations
359
XXVI. According to the law of nations, so far as external acts are concerned, no consideration is given to an inequality in terms which has been agreed to ; in what sense this may be said to be consistent with the law of nature
360-361
Chapter XIII On oaths
362-380
I. How great the force of an oath is, even in the opinion of heathen peoples
362-363
II. That a deliberate intention is required, that is, that a person has willed to take oath
363
III. That the words of an oath are binding in the sense in which it is believed that they were understood by the one to whom the oath was sworn
363-366
IV. When an oath procured by means of fraud is binding
366-367
V. That the words of an oath should not be stretched beyond the meaning supported by ordinary use
367-368
VI. That an oath to perform an unlawful act is not binding
368
VII. That an oath is not binding which hinders a greater moral good
368-369
VIII. That an oath is not binding to perform an act which is impossible
369
[246] IX. What if an act, for which an oath has been taken, is impossible for the time being ?
369
X. That an oath is sworn in the name of God, and in what sense
370
XI. But that an oath is sworn also in the name of other things with respect to God
370-371
XII. That an oath is binding even if one swears by false gods
371-372
XIII. The effects of an oath ; hence from an oath a twofold obligation arises, one at the moment of the oath, another afterward ; this is clearly explained
372
XIV. When, as a result of an oath, a right is acquired for a man and for God ; when for God alone
372-373
[248] XV. Refutation of the opinion that one who has given his oath to a pirate or a tyrant is not obligated to God
373-374
XVI. Whether one who has given his oath to a faithless person ought to keep his oath ; explanation, with a distinction
374
XVII. That when a person has given his oath to God alone his heir is in no degree obligated
375
XVIII. That he is not guilty of perjury who does not keep his oath to a person that does not wish to have it kept, or in case the special character of the person, to whom the oath was sworn because of that character, has been laid aside
375
XIX. When anything which is done contrary to an oath becomes void
375-376
XX. What power the act of superiors has with respect to that which a subject has sworn, or with respect to an oath given to a subject, is set forth, with distinctions
376-377
XXI. To what kind of oath the teachings of Christ in regard to not taking an oath are properly applicable
377-380
XXII. What unsworn pledge of good faith has by custom the force of an oath
380
[256] Chapter XIV On promises, contracts, and oaths of those who hold sovereign power
381-390
I. The opinion that restitution in full, which arises from municipal law, pertains to the acts of kings as such, is refuted ; also, that a king is not bound by an oath
381
II. Tο what acts of kings the laws apply is set forth, with distinctions
381-382
III. When a king is bound by his oath, and when not
382
IV. How far a king is bound with reference to things which he promised without cause
383
V. Application of what has been said about the force of law as regards the contracts of kings
383
VI. In what sense a king may rightly be said to be under obligation to his subjects by the law of nature only, and also by municipal law
383-384
VII. In what way a right lawfully obtained by subjects may be taken away
385
VIII. Here the distinction between rights gained by the law of nature and by municipal law is rejected
385
IX. Whether the contracts of kings are laws, and when
385-386
X. In what way the contracts of kings are binding on the heirs of all their possessions
386
XI. In what way those who succeed to the kingship only may he hound by the same contracts
386
XII. Tο what extent those who succeed to the kingship only may be bound by the same contracts
387-389
XIII. What grants of kings are revocable, and what are not, is set forth, with a distinction
389-390
XIV. Whether the rightful possessor of the throne is bound by the contracts of usurpers
390
Chapter XV On treaties and sponsions
391-408
I. What public conventions are
391
II. Conventions are divided into treaties, sponsions, and other agreements
391
III. The difference between treaties and sponsions ; to what extent sponsions are binding
391-392
IV. Rejection of the classification of treaties which Menippus made
393
V. The classification of treaties: first, treaties which establish the same rights as the law of nature ; whence this arises
393-394
[265] VI. Treaties which add something beyond the rights of the law of nature ; what treaties are on equal terms
394-396
VII. What treaties on unequal terms are ; such treaties, again, are subdivided
396-397
VIII. That treaties with those who are strangers to the true religion are permissible by the law of nature
397-
IX. That treaties with those who are strangers to the true religion are not, generally speaking, prohibited by the Hebraic law
397-401
X. That treaties with those who are strangers to the true religion are not prohibited by the Christian law
401-402
XI. Cautions in regard to such treaties
402-403
XII. That all Christians are under obligation to enter a league against the enemies of Christianity
403
XIII. Tο which ally help should by preference be given when several are at war, is explained, with distinctions
404-405
XIV. Whether an alliance may be considered as tacitly renewed
405
XV. Whether the one party may be freed by the perfidy of the other
405
XVI. Tο what the signers are bound if a sponsion signed by them is rejected ; also concerning the sponsion of the Caudine Forks
405-407
XVII. Whether a sponsion that has not been rejected is made binding through knowledge of it and through silence is set forth, with distinctions ; likewise concerning the sponsion of Luctatius
407-408
[275] Chapter XVI On interpretation
409-429
I. How promises are outwardly binding
409
II. If other implications are lacking, words are to be understood in their ordinary sense
409-410
III. Technical terms are to be explained according to their technical use
410
IV. Resort is to be had to conjectures in the case of ambiguous and contradictory expressions, or if conjectures naturally suggest themselves
411
V. Conjectures from the subject-matter
411-412
VI. Conjectures from the effect
412
VII. Conjectures from elements that are connected, either in origin or also in place
412
VIII. To what the conjecture drawn from reasonable motive applies ; and when, and how, it is in point
412-413
IX. The distinction between broad and narrow meanings
413
X. Division of promises into favourable, odious, mixed, and median
413-414
XI. The rejection of the distinction between contracts of good faith and those of strict legal right in relation to the acts of peoples and kings
414
XII. In accordance with the distinctions of meanings and promises stated, rules are formulated in regard to interpretations
414-415
XIII. Whether under the term ‘ allies ’ future allies are included, and in what degree ; also, concerning the treaty of the Romans with Hasdrubal, and similar controversies
415-417
XIV. In what way the clause, that one people may not make war without the consent of the other, ought to be interpreted
417
XV. Concerning the words ‘ Carthage shall be free ’
417-418
XVI. What compacts are to be considered personal, and what real, is set forth, with distinctions
418-419
XVII. That a treaty entered into with a king is continued with him though he may have been expelled from his kingdom
420
XVIII. That such a treaty does not apply to the usurper of a kingdom
420
XIX. To whom a promise is due if it was made to the one who should do something first, and several have done the thing at the same time
420-421
XX. A conjecture which presents itself in the one case broadens the meaning ; when this occurs
421-423
XXI. Herein also concerning the execution of a mandate in a different way
423
XXII. In the other case the coiijecture restricts the meaning ; and this may happen by reason of an original defect in the intent, which is inferred from its absurdity
423
XXIII. Conjecture may restrict the meaning by reason of the cessation of the only reason
424
XXIV. Conjecture may restrict the meaning by reason of a defect in the subject-matter
424
XXV. An observation concerning the conjectures last mentioned
424
XXVI. Or conjecture may restrict the meaning when a case which arises is incompatible with the intent; and this is assumed in regard to what is unlawful
424-425
XXVII. Conjecture may restrict the meaning when the condition is too burdensome as regards the act
425-427
XXVIII. Conjecture may be restricted in view of other indications, as when the parts of a document are in conflict
427
XXIX. What rules ought to be observed in such cases
427-428
XXX. That in a doubtful case a written document is not required for the validity of a contract
428
XXXI. The contracts of kings are not to be interpreted according to Roman law
429
XXXII. Whether the words of the one who accepts the condition, or the words of the one who offers it, ought to carry greater weight, is set forth, with a distinction
429
XXVIII. Conjecture may be restricted in view of other indications, as when the farts of a document are in conflict
427
XXIX. What rules ought to be observed in such cases
427-428
XXX. That in a doubtful case a written document is not required for the validity of a contract
428
XXXI. The contracts of kings are not to be interpreted according to Roman law
429
XXXII. Whether the words of the one who accepts the condition, or the words of the one who offers it, ought to carry greater weight, is set forth, with a distinction
429
Chapter XVII On damage caused through injury, and the obligation arising therefrom
430-437
I. That fault creates the obligation to make good the loss
430
II. That damage is understood to be that which conflicts with one’s right taken in a strict sense
430-431
III. That aptitude must be carejully distinguished from legal right in a strict sense, when they coexist
431
IV. That damage extends also to income
431-432
V. How the principle stated applies to the cessation of income
432
VI. Those who by their act cause damage primarily
432
VII. Those who by their act cause damage secondarily
432
VIII. Likewise those who by not doing what they ought cause damage primarily
432
IX. Those who by not doing as they ought cause damage secondarily
432-433
X. What kind of effective participation in the act is requisite to create such obligation
433
XI. In what order such persons are held liable
433
XII. That the liability is extended even to resulting damage
433-434
XIII. An example in homicide
434
XIV. An example of one who has used violence in a different way
434
XV. Of the adulterer and seducer
434-435
XVI. Of a thief, robber, and others
435
XVII. Of one, who has procured a promise through deceit or an unjust fear
435
XVIII. What if the promise has been motived by a just fear according to the law of nature ?
435
XIX. What of the fear, which is considered just by the law of nations ?
435-436
XX. To what extent civil authorities are liable for loss caused by their subjects ; wherein is the question of captures made at sea from allies contrary to public command
436-437
XXI.—That according to the law of nature no one is liable for damage done by his animal or his vessel without his fault
437
XXII.—That damage may be caused to reputation and honour, and how it may be repaired
437
Chapter XVIII On the right of legation
438-449
I. That certain obligations, such as the right of legation, have their origin in the law of nations
438-
II. Among whom the right of legation is in force
439-440
III. Whether an embassy ought always to be admitted
440-441
IV. Against ambassadors, who are undertaking dangerous missions, defence is permissible, but not the exaction of a penalty
441-445
V. That the person to whom, the ambassador was not sent is not bound by the right of legation
445-446
VI. That the enemy to whom an ambassador has been sent is bound by the law
446
VII. That the right of retaliation cannot be claimed against ambassadors
447
VIII. The right of ambassadors is also extended to the suite of an ambassador, if the ambassador has desired it
447-448
IX. The right of ambassadors is extended likewise to their movable goods
448
X. Examples of an obligation without the right of compulsion
448-449
XI. Of how great importance this right of legation is
449
Chapter XIX On the right of sepulchre
450-461
I. The right of burial of the dead has its origin in the same law of nations
450-452
II. Whence the right arose
452-455
III. That burial is due also to public enemies
455-456
IV. Whether the right of burial is obligatory in the case of notorious criminals
457-458
V. Whether the right of burial is obligatory in the case of those who kill themselves
458-461
VI. What other rights impose obligation by virtue of the law of nations
461
Chapter XX On punishments
462-521
I. Definition and origin of -punishment
462-463
II. That punishment is related to expletive justice, and in what way
463-465
III. That nature does not determine to whom punishment is due, but that according to the law of nature those free from like offences may exact punishment
465-466
IV. That punishment having in view some advantage must among men be inflicted differently than by God ; and why
466-467
V. In what sense vengeance may be forbidden by nature
467-469
VI. The threefold advantage of punishment
469-470
VII. Proof that punishment for the good of the wrong-doer may be exacted by any one at all according to the law of nature
470-471
VIII. Likewise for the good of him who has been wronged, where it concerns vengeance permitted by universal common law
472-475
IX. Likewise for the good of the whole
475-478
X. What the law of the Gospel has established in this matter
478-482
XI. The answer to the argument drawn from the mercy of God revealed in the Gospel
482-483
XII. Answer to the argument drawn from the exclusion of repentance
483-484
XIII. A rejection of incomplete classifications of punishments
484-485
XIV. It is not safe for Christians, as private citizens, to exact punishment, even when universal common law allows it
485
XV. Neither should Christians of their own accord be too zealous in making accusations
485-486
XVI. Nor should Christians seek the office of criminal judge
486
XVII. The distinction between human laws which confer the right to kill as a punishment and those which merely give impunity for such action
486-487
XVIII. Internal acts are not punishable by men
487
XIX. Extrinsic acts which human frailty cannot avoid are not punishable by men
488-489
XX. Acts by which human society is not injured, directly or indirectly, are not punishable by men. The explanation thereof
489
XXI. A refutation of the view that pardon is never permissible
489-490
XXII. Proof that pardon is permissible prior to the penal law
490-491
[331] XXIII. But pardon is not permissible in all cases
491
XXIV. Proof that pardon is permissible even after the establishment of the penal law
491-492
XXV. What intrinsic causes are sufficient to cause the suspension of the law
492
XXVI. What extrinsic causes are sufficient
492-493
XXVII. Rejection of the view that there is no just cause to suspend the law, unless it is one that is contained in the law as an implied exception
493-494
XXVIII. The measure of punishment according to what is deserved
494
XXIX. A consideration, in this connexion, of the causes which lead to crime, and a comparison of these with one another
494-495
XXX. Also a consideration of the causes that should have restrained from sin ; with a discussion of the order of the commandments of the decalogue that apply to one's neighbour, and some other things
495-497
XXXI. Also the inclination of the sinner toward incentives to and deterrents from sinning, which is considered from various points of view
497-498
XXXII. The desert of punishment may be extended to include a greater harm than the sinner has actually inflicted. The reasons therefor
498-499
XXXIII. Rejection of the idea of a harmonic proportion in punishments
499-500
XXXIV. Punishment may be mitigated on the ground of regard for others, unless a greater regard for others opposes
500
XXXV. How the opportunity to commit sin may urge to its punishment ; also how the habit of sinning may urge to the punishment of the sin or dissuade from it
500-501
XXXVI. The use of clemency in mitigating punishments
501-502
XXXVII. What the Jews and the Romans thought should be taken into consideration in punishments is brought into relation with the foregoing discussion
502
XXXVIII. On war waged to inflict punishment
502-503
XXXIX. By distinguishing various cases, it is explained whether a war waged to punish wrongs that have been merely attempted is just
503-504
XL. A discussion whether kings and peoples may rightly wage war on account of things done contrary to the law of nature, although not against them or their subjects ; with a refutation of the view that the law of nature requires right of jurisdiction for the exaction of punishment
504-506
XLI. The law of nature must be distinguished from widely current national customs
507
XLII. The law of nature must be distinguished also from the Divine law that is not voluntarily recognized by all
507
XLIII. In the law of nature we must distinguish between what is evident and what is not evident
507-508
XLIV. Whether war may be waged on account of crimes against God
508-510
XLV. What ideas of God are most generally accepted ; and how these are indicated in the first commandments of the Decalogue
510-512
XLVI. Those who first do violence to these common ideas may he punished
513-514
XLVII. But we may not punish others in like manner, as is shown by an argument from the Hebraic law
514-516
XLVIII. Wars cannot justly be waged against those who are unwilling to accept the Christian religion
516-517
XLIX. Wars are justly waged against those who treat Christians with cruelty for the sake of their religion alone
517-518
L. Wars may not be justly waged against those who err in the interpretation of the Divine law ; as is proven by authorities and examples
518-521
LI.—But war may justly be waged against those who show impiety toward the gods they believe in
521
Chapter XXI On the sharing of punishments
522-545
I. How punishment may pass to those who have shared in the crime
522-523
II. A community, or its rulers, may be held responsible for the crime of a subject if they know of it and do not prevent it when they could and should prevent it
523-526
III. Likewise a community, or its rulers, may be held responsible for refuge afforded to those who have done wrong elsewhere
526
IV. Such responsibility rests upon a community or its rulers unless they either punish or surrender the guilty parties, as is shown by examples
527-529
V. The rights of suppliants belong to the unfortunate, and not to the guilty, with exceptions
530-533
VI. Nevertheless suppliants are to be protected pending the hearing of their case ; under what law the hearing is to be conducted
533-534
VII. How subjects share in the crimes of their rulers, and members of a community in those of the community ; and how the punishment of a community differs from that of individuals
534-535
VIII. How long the right of inflicting punishment upon a community continues
535-536
IX. Whether punishment may be shared without sharing the crime
537
X. The distinction between that which is inflicted directly and that which comes as a consequence
537-538
XI. The distinction between what is done owing to the occasion of a crime and what is done owing to the cause of the crime
538-539
XII. That, properly speaking, no one may be justly punished for another’s wrong, and why
539
XIII. That children may not be punished for the sins of their parents
539-540
XIV. Answer is made concerning the acts of God with regard to the children of the wicked
541-543
XV. Much the less are other relatives to be punished
543
XVI. Nevertheless to children and relatives of the guilty something may be denied which they otherwise could have had ; instances thereof
543
XVII. Subjects may not properly be punished for a wrong committed by their king
543-544
XVIII. Individuals, who have not consented thereto, cannot be punished for the wrong-doing of the community
544
XIX. Heirs are not subject to punishment as such ; reasons therefor
544-545
XX. Nevertheless heirs may be subject to punishment if this has passed over into an obligation of another kind
545
[384] Chapter XXII On unjust causes [of wars]
546-556
I. The distinction between justifiable and persuasive causes is explained
546-547
II. Wars which lack causes of either sort are wars of savages
547
III. Wars which have persuasive but not justifying causes are wars of robbers
547-548
IV. There are certain causes which present a false appearance of justice
549
V. Such a cause is the fear of something uncertain
549
VI. Another such cause is advantage apart from necessity
549
VII. A cause of war presenting the appearance of justice is the refusal of marriage, when there is a great abundance of marriageable women
550
VIII. Such a cause, again, is the desire for richer land
550
IX. Such a cause is also the discovery of things previously taken over by others
550
X. What course is to be followed if the previous occupants are insane
550
XI. An unjust cause of war is the desire for freedom among a subject people
551
[387] XII. An unjust cause of war also is the desire to rule others against their will on the pretext that it is for their good
551
XIII. An unjust cause of war is the title to universal empire which some give to the Emperor, and which is shown to be inapplicable
551-552
XIV. An unjust cause of war is the title to universal empire which others give to the Church, and which also is shown to be inapplicable
553-554
XV. An unjust cause of war is also the desire to fulfil prophecies, without the command of God
555
XVI. An unjust cause of war is also the desire to obtain something that is owed by an obligation not strictly legal but arising from some other source
555-556
XVII. The difference between a war the cause of which is unjust and a war in which there is a wrong of another kind ; and the different effects of each
556
Chapter XXIII On doubtful causes of war
557-566
I. On the source of the causes of doubt in moral questions
557
[394] II. Nothing is to be done contrary to the dictates of one’s mind, however erroneous they may be
557-558
III. One's judgement may be influenced in either direction by arguments from facts
558
IV. One's judgement may be influenced in either direction by authority
558-559
V. If in a weighty matter there is doubt on both sides, and one of two courses must be chosen, that which is the safer is to be adopted
559-560
VI. Whence it follows that in case of doubt we must refrain from war
560
VII. First, war may be obviated by a conference
560-561
VIII. Second, war may be obviated by arbitration ; with a discussion of the duty of Christian kings in regard to warring parties
561-563
IX. Third, war may be obviated even by lot
563
X. Whether single combat may be permitted as a means of avoiding war
563-564
XI.—Where the doubt on either side is equal, he who is in possession has the more advantageous position
564-565
[398] XII. When the doubt on either side is equal, if neither party is in possession the thing under dispute should be divided
565
XIII. The question whether a war may be just from the view-point of both parties is discussed, with many qualifications
565-566
Chapter XXIV Warnings not to undertake war rashly, even for just causes
567-577
I. Often a right should be given up in order to avoid war
567
II. Especially the right to inflict punishments ought to be given up in order to avoid war
568-569
III. A right should be given up, especially by a king who has been wronged, in order to avoid war
569-570
IV. Even for the sake of one's self and one's dependants a ruler must often refrain from war
570-571
V. Rules dictated by prudence regarding the choice between things that are good
571-573
VI. An example in a deliberation between devotion to freedom and devotion to peace ; whereby the slaughter of a people may be avoided
573-574
VII. He who is not much the stronger ought to refrain from exacting penalties
574-575
VIII. It results that war is not to be undertaken, unless of necessity
575
IX. Again, war is not to be undertaken save from a most weighty cause at a most opportune time
575-576
X. The evils of war placed, before our eyes
576-577
[411] Chapter XXV On the causes of undertaking war on behalf of others
578-586
I. War may rightfully he undertaken on behalf of subjects
578
II. Yet war is not always to be undertaken on behalf of subjects
578
III. Whether an innocent subject may be surrendered to an enemy, in order that danger may be avoided
579-580
IV. Wars may rightfully be undertaken also on behalf of allies of equal or unequal standing
581
V. Wars may rightfully be undertaken on behalf of friends
581
VI. Wars, finally, may rightfully be undertaken on behalf of any persons whatsoever
582
VII. Nevertheless the obligation to undertake war may be disregarded without wrong, if one fears for himself, or even for the life of an innocent person
582-583
VIII. The question whether a war for the defence of subjects of another power is rightful is explained by a distinction
583-584
IX. Military alliances and mercenary service without dissemination regarding the causes of war are unjust
585-586
X. It is also particularly wrong to take service merely for the sake of plunder or pay
586
[417] Chapter XXVI On just causes for war waged by those who are under the rule of another
587-595
I. Who may be said to be under the rule of another
587
II. What those under the rule of another should do if they are summoned to share in deliberation, or have a free choice of action
587
III. If those under the rule of another should be ordered to go to war, and should believe the cause of the war to be unjust, they ought not to serve
587-590
IV. What they who are under the rule of another, and are ordered to go to war, should do if they are in doubt
590-594
V. Sense of duty requires that subjects who doubt in regard to the justness of a war should be spared, but the burden of an extraordinary tax may be imposed upon them
594
VI. When it may be just for subjects to bear arms in a war that is unjust